Wednesday, August 8, 2012

Unity and the Vote


If you want to purchase the right to one vote within Fonterra, you can do so for $4520.  Purchasing rights within Fonterra will now be easier in the future thanks to TAF.  Without knowing it, the acceptance of TAF has also enhanced the role of markets within the cooperative to allocate all things, including those things we traditionally placed non-market values on.  But importantly, we didn’t arrive at this state through a deliberate choice. To unify the cooperative, we must now look at how we arrived here and whether this is in our long-term best interests.
To investigate how this happened, consider this:
Should votes within Fonterra be subject to market share, tradeable and therefore viewed as private property, or rather seen as a civic responsibility to the cooperative, and therefore an obligation of membership?  
This is actually a question about the appropriateness of markets without limits within the cooperative.  But why should we worry that we are moving towards a cooperative in which everything is up for sale?  For two reasons: one is about inequality, the other is about corruption.
Consider inequality: Larger farmers who have more money invested in the cooperative should have a greater say because they have more to loose.
 This sounds like a strong market based argument, but implicit in this comment is that smaller farmers are less able to make appropriate decisions for the good of the cooperative because supply size is the best measure of democratic competency.  Of course rational thought says that this argument is flawed, but for the last 10 years, this argument has prevailed largely unchallenged.  For ten years, those with more means have mattered more.
The second reason, corruption, is about the corrosive nature of markets.  Markets change the way we view the things being exchanged.  When we decide that certain things should be tradable, we decide, at least implicitly, that it is appropriate to treat them as commodities, as instruments of profits and use. This means that if you have the ability to influence the outcome of a vote, you would be more inclined to vote towards an outcome that is to your personal advantage. Conversely, if you had no more ability to influence the result than any other member you would be more inclined to vote towards the collective good, believing that everyone else would do the same too.  
Markets should have limits within the cooperative.  Markets promote inequality and corrupt the non-market values of the things they allocate.  They change member attitudes towards the value of the cooperative, towards other members, and towards working together for the collective good.
Encouraging markets into all areas of our cooperative will not promote unity.  A 66% majority of a market-based vote might be the easy way to claim unity, but we all know that to truly have cohesion within the cooperative requires brave leadership.  Leaders who can step back from heady market values and rediscover the truly priceless non-market values that can unit us and drive dairying sustainably into the future.

FONTERRA GOVERNANCE HAS FAILED TAF


When farmers voted to investigate the possibility of a TAF market in 2010, the vote was underpinned by the conviction that farmer members held for the cooperative’s capital structure that ownership and control are non-negotiable.  What was never investigated by the governance team within Fonterra developing the TAF model was the principle behind this conviction.  The principle is that ownership and control allows members to work collectively towards a common good, a way in which all Fonterra members will thrive now and in the future.
The final model of TAF is of a share trading market that promotes individual rights and encourages consumer-like behaviours.  It is not clear how this model supports the principle of enhancing the collective unity of the cooperative or the common good. The final TAF model supports the conviction but confounds the principle. This is why there is increasing uncertainty recently from the general shareholding on the validity of TAF as a capital structure model that is well served for a strong cooperative.
The TAF model itself is very clever and does, in my opinion, exactly what has been asked of it.  However, what has been asked is inconsistent with normal, modern cooperative governance practices.  The TAF model was developed to reduce redemption risk for the cooperative.  In 2008/9 the cooperative suffered heavily from redemption and the governors saw this as a market failure, rather than the constitutional failure which it was. The current governors of Fonterra view their role as being neutral in matters of the common good, allowing individual members the freedoms to pursue their own interests through the cooperative. As a result, they see themselves as fixes of market failures, with a market-mimicking style of governance. This is where the real risk of demutualisation lies.
Demutualisation will happen when TAF market fails, or falters, in the future. Using this market-mimicking style of governance, our leaders will look to fix the problem with a larger, deeper, more liquid market.  We know this for sure as this is how the issue of redemption has been dealt with, how the decision for the 2nd vote was arrived at, and is behaviour that is consistent with current internal Board policies based on the spurious science of cost/benefit analysis.
Governors using market-mimicking governance struggle with working through the sometimes emotive and controversial opinions and convictions that come from encouraging democratic dialogue within a diverse shareholder base.  In an attempt to remove the subjective nature of these emotions, governors strive to reach decisions from a more scientific basis and use cost/benefit analysis to this end.
Cost/benefit analysis involves weighting the benefit of implementing a new policy or project against the costs of implementing it or not, and a decision is made based on the results. The problem with this kind of analysis is in assigning value to those things that we struggle to value in the first place, things such as goodwill, solidarity, succession, loyalty and sustainability.  How these things are valued will alter the results of cost/benefit analysis and renders it insufficient as a complete instrument for governance.  This is why modern governance methods that include member consultation and engagement yield far more consistent and enduring results. This is because it allows governors to arrive at a multi-dimensional understanding of member expectations based on the three strands of just governance; Welfare, Rights and Virtues.
It will be premature for members to enable TAF to proceed without stronger constitutional safeguards around enhancing democratic self-rule and the collective common good of the cooperative. TAF, although a cleaver concept, has not demonstrated how it strengthens or even supports the cooperative and the collective nature of the business for reasons beyond permanency of capital.  Members are becoming increasingly aware that TAF, without a stronger constitutional foundation, will critically and irreversibly weaken the collective strength of the cooperative nature of the business, despite offering increased financial strength to the capital structure in the short term.
Our governors have failed to recognise that right of individuals should not come before the common good, rather the right should be a consequence of the good. It is unfortunate that the cooperative has failed to demonstrate the qualities of leadership required to circumvent this politically delicate situation earlier.  This painful situation must now be born by whole the cooperative, putting members in a very difficult predicament that they are yet to have genuine dialogue on.

TAF and critical thinking


The basis for my concern for the TAF proposal is that the governance of Fonterra appears to lack critical thinking and therefore rational judgement. I would never dispute the absolute importance of ensuring any governance decision meets robust economic scrutiny, but higher reasoning suggests that it should never be the primary motive for decisions. When governance decisions of a cooperative are made to meet economic desires or market preferences firstly, they are without a reasoned and rational judgement basis, and as a result are at the mercy of circumstance rather than being free and unburdened to shape the cooperative’s destiny. Continuous flip-flopping of policy and the protracted capital structure debate are examples how leadership have tied the cooperative to the arbitrary nature of their markets, both internal and external. This is in contrast to a rational judgement position that would allow the governors to unlock the full potential of the cooperative for its members.
Without policy arrived at from a rational judgement basis, the cooperative will lack a unified and clear vision of the future for members.  Members become confused and frustrated with continually changing policy and this generates mistrust of the leaders and their motives, and at times, outrage for decisions that appear dictatorial.  It has been argued many times that these outbursts of anger are emotive reactions to policy members do not, or have not taken the time to fully understand.  But in dismissing this anger, the governors fail to recognise that anger, and especially outrage, are the specific reactions people have to injustices imposed upon them. People are rational beings capable of reason and therefore should be treated justly and with respect.  You can only be ensured that you consistently and deliberately treat people justly if you act with rational judgement in dealings with them.
Governance that is founded on rational judgement is stronger than arbitrary decisions. It is stronger and more enduring because in addition to being able to promote economic sustainability it offers direction to strategy, galvanises membership and enhances the collective recourse value of Fonterra. It also sends a clear message to the government and the wider community that the organisation stands for something of value, and that value is worth protecting.  How individual Boards judge what is right and just is for each board to determine, but through judgement and rational reason rather than arbitrary reaction, governance decisions must be made.
To illustrate my point, I will use environmental sustainability as an example.  It was identified that the approach to environmental sustainability by Fonterra and it farmers’ is becoming increasingly important to markets, both here and overseas.  In response Fonterra has launched a concerted environmental sustainability program throughout its sites and began to introduce a number of punitive measures to try to fast-track farmers into improving their environmental compliance performance and meet customer expectations.  The result was general outrage from the membership base and this was scaled back to the introduction of urgent, but somewhat ad hoc, on-farm environmental support programs such as every farm every day. The decision to undertake these measures was driven entirely by economic need.  The decision to undertake operations sustainably should have been from a rational moral judgement first. Fonterra should choose to participate in environmental sustainability because the governors have engaged with members to understand their positions on the issue, then stripped these arguments back and rationally evaluated them.  From this evaluation they would then drawn a reasoned judgement about the environment having an intrinsic value that is worth protecting for Fonterra, its farmers and the community it serves. Therefore working to improve environmental sustainability becomes the right thing to do for the cooperative and its members.
It could be argued that regardless of the approach, the result still remains the same; environmental sustainably.  But this is only true in the short term.  Once the whims of the market move in another direction, so too will the policy and the commitment that comes with it. The fundamental difference between the two approaches is that a decision based primarily on economics uses environmental sustainability as a means to an end.  Governance based on rational judgement would view environmental sustainability as an end in itself. When the leadership always follows a rational judgement position, it sends a consistent message to members, and the wider community, that Fonterra wants to make a meaningful difference for reasons beyond “it makes good commercial sense.”  People want to interact with an organisation that treats them and the things they value justly.  This behaviour creates a powerful competitive advantage; but this should not be the motive in itself.
The practice of reacting primarily to economic stimuli and market pressures for making governance decisions is why I still hold grave concerns for the TAF proposal.
The most enduring reasons that have been presented to me as the driving purposes for the TAF proposal is to remove redemption risk and free up capital to pursue economic options as part of the strategic plan.  What has not been made clear is the how the capital structure plan is intended to support and protect the collective resource value of Fonterra.  Although some issues surrounding this have been addressed in-part by the proposal, their handling is somewhat clumsy and critically impinges on the justice of such a proposal.   On the face of it, it appears that this proposal presents a capital structure that uses members’ rights and the collective resource value of Fonterra to galvanise the economic flexibility of the company, rather than to galvanise member rights and preserve the collective resource value as the end in itself.  Below I present my reasoning on how I arrived at this position.
(It is important to note that I am not supporting the current system as an alternative as this too is heavily flawed and fails the critical thinking test.)
My first clue to the reasoning of TAF comes from when I question how free the TAF market will be. In a regular investor market a potential investor is free to choose, when, how often, and to what levels they participate. This means investors are free to participate with the market as they choose, creating a free market.  In contrast, farmer members are coerced in their participation by the compliance aspect of membership into the cooperative.  The primary motivation for participating in the TAF market by cooperative members is not investment, rather access to the cooperative, investment is secondary. This means that to participate with the cooperative to supply milk, farmers are required to participate with the market. This policy works on the assumption that because all members of Fonterra are farmers, they are also equally capable as investors.  This position is morally contingent in so much as their success in this market is contingent on their natural talents and abilities or their opportunities to acquire satisfactory trading skills. Farmers are choosing to be farmers but are being coerced into being investment traders.  As farmers are also bound in the level they can participate due to the membership compliance requirements I feel that there is also a material level of coercion in their freedom to interact with the market, which is in addition to their desire to even engage. This inequity in access to the market between farmers and investors could expose the cooperative to free-riding on the capital value and the distributable profit.
The second clue to the reasoning comes from member access.  Under the current constitution, members wishing to access the cooperative are free to transact directly with the cooperative.  Under the TAF proposal, farmers wishing to join or increase membership in the cooperative can only do so on the condition that they compete for membership through the market.   Making supply conditional, transfers members’ rights from a collective constitutional arrangement to an individual contractual agreement. It could be argued that this is now a condition of supply and anyone wishing to supply the cooperative must adhere to the rule of supply. This reasoning is flawed as it implies that producing milk constitutes consent to participate in the market because farmers must engage with the market if they receive services.  It moves consent from explicit to tacit. Tacit consent to compete in the market in this case means that the agreement may not be wholly voluntary, due to the superior bargaining position of Fonterra created by the perishable nature of milk.  It moves membership from a position of freedom to one of condition.
The third clue to the reasoning is how membership entitlements are protected.  Take as an example two farmers.  Farmer A meets the share standard to supply based on their three-year rolling average.  This farmer chooses to place 10% of their shares into the fund.  In effect has laid out total capital for 100% of supply minus the 10% that he has re-couped by placing shares into the fund.  Farmer B also meets the share standard to supply based on his three-year rolling average.  This farmer has a bumper year producing 10% above this three-year average, a one-off year, and now has in effect invested capital for 100% of supply minus 10%. Each farmer is supplying 10% more than the shareholding they have money invested in the cooperative for.  Both qualify for full membership by meeting the three-year rolling average share standard, but only one, farmer A, will be entitled to the just deserts of this membership (full milk price and full voting rights).  If farmer B wishes to also receive the just deserts, he is forced to engage with the market in addition to meeting the share standard for membership.  This creates an inequity in membership entitlements that is not equally reflected in membership obligations.  This action appears to put the need for liquidity in the market ahead of membership rights.
The forth clue to the reasoning is the milk pricing mechanism.  In investor owned companies, producers of raw products are contracted to supply a pre-determined volume of goods for a particular price.  If the processor experiences unforseen increases in the cost of producing their product that they are unable to pass on the their customers, the shortfall for this amount would be met by investors through reduced distributable profit, not by the supplier of the raw materials that are contracted at a fixed price.  This is in contrast to Fonterra where this shortfall would not come from distributable profit, rather the milk price as this fits with the milk pricing formula.  The important thing to note with dairy cooperatives is that the farm-gate milk price is set after the company knows what it has achieved from the market, not before as is the case with other types of contractual supply. This means that the success or failure of NZ milk supply must be born entirely by the suppliers, as the owners of the milk, because the profit from the value-add portion of the business must be distributed as dividend and not subsidise the performance of NZ milk.  This model works well in times of market largess because an economic based policy dictates milk price will be the focus.  This becomes an issue when the market shifts and greater economic rewards can be found for value-add, or more worryingly, off-shore supply (distributable profit); as apposed to enhancing and following the collective purpose. This puts Fonterra’s economic growth needs ahead of the collective purpose.
My overall assessment of the TAF proposal is that Management have produced a clever option that does exactly what was asked of it. Unfortunately I have serious concerns about what was asked. It appears that the Board has failed to match the proposal to the collective purpose of the cooperative resulting in a miss-match of synergies. The four objections I presented are just off the top of my head, and I know others would be found if critical thinking was applied to the whole proposal in any great detail.   The mere existence of these objections says that no reasoned judgement has been applied. The only judgement appears to have been whether it met the financial objectives for restructuring set by management. There is no rational judgement as to rights, responsibilities, entitlements, desirable virtues, just deserts, honours, loyalties and collective purpose that TAF should encourage, protect and enhance.  The proposal is about securing Fonterra’s financial future alone.  This proposal appears to use the inter-generational collective resource value and members’ rights to achieve this end, rather than the protection of this value and these rights being the end in itself.

Saturday, February 11, 2012

What is the Government doing with DIRA?


The Government has failed the people of New Zealand with their DIRA review.  This legislation is not about taxing those with surplus incomes and re-distributing it as a civic good, rather its better viewed for what it is; the Government sanctioned enforced re-distribution of assets from a group of NZ citizens to foreign owned companies. 
1.       Compensation does not reflect free market exchange
a.       Ability of private processors to drive down the milk price.
b.      Increased value of the raw milk for on-demand uptake.
c.       Inability for individual farmers to refuse consent to participate in the scheme if they feel compensation is inadequate.
2.       There is no civic duty aspect
a.       The purpose of the original DIRA regulations is not being met.
b.      Obligations do not reflect entitlements for participating in the scheme.

1.       Collective consent is tainted.
a.       Farmers could not have known how they would feel about corporate free-riders on the cooperative.
b.      The honour of NZ farmers as world leaders in the cooperative model is under threat.


The Raw Milk Regulations works on the premise of taking some milk from the larger processor and re-distributing it to some smaller processors who are less able to source the milk therefore enhancing the utility of the dairy industry as a whole within New Zealand.  This theory works on the assumption that the environment is of a larger processor dominating the NZ milk supply where smaller processors are trying to emerge to add competition at the farm-gate price and choices for farmers around who to supply.  This reasoning is flawed because it misunderstands the cooperative model.  The cooperative is actually individual farmers processing their own milk through a collective resource system, and are doing it in an organised way, creating the Fonterra organisation. This means that all farmers using Fonterra are in-fact still the legal owners of the milk and must bear the responsibilities and receive the rewards that ownership of the milk bestows.  The justness of this proposal critically hinges on whether compensation to farmers for their milk reflects a genuine free-market exchange, is any civic duty met and how untainted is original consent given by farmers to participate in DIRA.

Firstly I will explore the compensation to the NZ farmers for their raw milk (products of their time and labour) that is removed from them, and whether the farmers’ compensation reflects what would be achievable in a free market exchange. To investigate this we look at the farm-gate milk price.  It is important to note that the farm-gate milk price for a cooperative is set after the company knows what it has achieved from the market, not before which would be the case if this was a type of contractual supply to a company independent of the individual farmer’s business. This means that the success or failure of NZ milk supply must be born entirely by the suppliers, as owners of the product. Due to the mismatch in size between the domestic market and the domestic milk supply, the majority of the value for the milk produced in NZ comes from exporting it.  By farmers organising themselves into a way which, for the most part, creates a single point of sale from NZ enhances the profitability of the saleable product, and therefore the reward each farmer is able to achieve for their milk.  The emergence of private export processors, supported by the DIRA regulations, has seen this position as a single point of sale for NZ dairy products weakened.  This action has a negative effect on the farm-gate milk price, because as discussed before, the milk price is set after it is known what the market will pay, not before.  Farmers are now not able to maximise their income from the cross-boarder sale of milk due to increased competition coming from NZ and the decreased collective volumes available to sell. This means that private processors subsidized by DIRA can weaken the farm-gate price, the very price that determines the justness of the confiscated raw milk from individual farmers.  The farm-gate milk price now becomes inadequate to reason a fair exchange due to the superior ability of private processors to influence the market ahead of individual farmers.

The ability of private processors to choose when they take raw milk intrinsically increases the value of this raw milk to them, as it allows them to maximise their processing capacity for longer, maximising their profitability.  This further value added to the raw milk by the regulations is not reflected in the basic milk price alone; meaning the milk-price alone is not adequate compensation.  It is critical to ensure the compensation is fair as individual farmers do not actually have the freedom to refuse participation in the scheme if they do not feel compensation is just. 

The second aspect to this claim is whether the NZ public are benefiting from the redistribution of the raw milk and any civic responsibility is being met.  Part of the purpose for the DIRA regulations was to ensure that the NZ public would have adequate competition in the supermarket to keep dairy products affordable.  The success of this aspect cannot be accurately measured because despite the high level of uptake from new and established private processors, the majority of the milk is being exported rather than finding its way to the domestic market.  The reason for this is that the entitlements processors receive for accessing the Raw Milk scheme are not met with any obligations around promoting domestic competition, or to the NZ dairy industry as a whole.  The ability to receive entitlements without obligation is a gaping injustice in the scheme and one that encourages free-riding on the collective resource value of Fonterra to maximise profits for overseas investors.

The third aspect to this claim is how this lack of obligations and the consequential free-riding on the farmers’ collective resource system of Fonterra, taints the original collective consent the Fonterra farmers gave when the scheme was set up.  Farmers collectively entered into consent for the scheme to enable the formation of Fonterra, but would have been unable to know at the time that the scheme would not produce the originally consulted on outcomes and expose the cooperative to the free-riding on capital by private processors, and critically, how they would feel about this.  There is also the question of honorific value in forcibly removing the fruits of farmers’ time and labour.  Farmers have worked for a number of generations to increase the strength of the cooperative model and are proud of their position in New Zealand and on the world stage as an example of the power of the cooperative model.  The DIRA scheme undermines this honour and sends a message to the NZ public that the government does not value individual producers of export products working collectively to take on larger and better geographically positioned countries successfully.

This scheme amounts to nothing more than a re-distribution of income and wealth away from NZ farmers to overseas based investors.  It empowers private processors to free-ride on the cooperative model for their own ends.  This behaviour does not support or enhance the purpose of the original legislation and does not add to the civic good.  The lack of obligations attached to the entitlements seriously erodes the fairness of the scheme.  Tainted consent and the derogation of fair compensation coupled with the lack of freedom for individual farmers to refuse participation in the scheme makes the scheme unjust to those it was intended to protect; the NZ farmer and the NZ public.

As minimum measures to protect the NZ farmer and the NZ public we believe that the following actions are the least the government can take to ensure a basic level of justice is restored.

  • ·         Limit the number of years a private processor can access the scheme.
  • ·         Remove virtual processors.
  • ·         Failure to uptake one month should constitute withdrawing from the scheme for that season.
  • ·         Introduce some form of obligation to the NZ domestic market for those that access the scheme, at least while they are in the scheme.